From owner-qed Thu Nov 3 07:52:36 1994 Received: from localhost (listserv@localhost) by antares.mcs.anl.gov (8.6.4/8.6.4) id HAA09494 for qed-out; Thu, 3 Nov 1994 07:52:20 -0600 Received: from lapsene.mii.lu.lv (root@lapsene.mii.lu.lv [159.148.60.2]) by antares.mcs.anl.gov (8.6.4/8.6.4) with SMTP id HAA09480 for ; Thu, 3 Nov 1994 07:50:46 -0600 Received: from sisenis.mii.lu.lv by lapsene.mii.lu.lv with SMTP id AA03234 (5.67a8/IDA-1.4.4 for ); Thu, 3 Nov 1994 15:50:35 +0200 Received: by sisenis.mii.lu.lv id AA14700 (5.67a8/IDA-1.4.4 for QED discussions ); Thu, 3 Nov 1994 15:50:32 +0200 Date: Thu, 3 Nov 1994 15:50:28 +0200 (EET) From: Karlis Podnieks To: QED discussions Subject: Semantics Message-Id: Mime-Version: 1.0 Content-Type: TEXT/PLAIN; charset=US-ASCII Sender: owner-qed@mcs.anl.gov Precedence: bulk K.Podnieks, Dr.Math. podnieks@mii.lu.lv PLATONISM, INTUITION AND THE NATURE OF MATHEMATICS Continued from #2. The mathematical method is (by definition) investigation of fixed models. What is then mathematics itself? Models can be more or less general (let us compare, for example, arithmetic of natural numbers, the relativity theory and some model of the solar system). Very specific models will be investigated better under management of specialists who are creating and using them. A combination of special experience with sufficient experience in mathematics (in one person or in a team) will be here the most efficient strategy. But the investigation of more general models which can be applied to many different specific models draws up the contents of a specific branch of science which is called mathematics. For example, the Calculus has many applications in various fields and, therefore, it is a striking example of a theory which undoubtedly belongs to mathematics. On the other hand, a model of solar system (used, for example, for exact prediction of eclipses) is too specific to be encountered as part of mathematics (although it is surely a mathematical model). The fixed character of mathematical models and theories is simultaneously the force and the weakness of mathematics. The ability of mathematicians to obtain maximum of information from minimum of premises has shown its efficiency in science and technique many times. But, the other side of this force is weakness: no concrete fixed model (theory) can solve all problems arising in science (or even in mathematics itself). An excellent confirmation of this thesis was given in the famous incompleteness theorem of K.Goedel. And one more weakness. Mathematics, being distracted from real problems of other fields, controlled only by its "internal needs", is getting more and more uncontrollable. Theories and whole branches of mathematics are developed, which do not have and cannot have any applications to real problems. Polish writer Stanislav Lem joked in his book "Summa Technologiae": a mathematician is like a mad tailor: he is making "all possible clothes" and hopes to make also something suitable for dressing... . As we have seen this problem is due to the very nature of mathematical method. No other branch of science knows such problems. Mathematicians have learned ability "to live" (literally!) in the world of mathematical concepts and even (while working on some concrete problem) - in a very specific "world" of a concrete model. Investigation of models is mathematician's goal for goal's sake, during their work they disregard the existence of the reality behind the model. Here we have the main source of the creative power of mathematics: in this way, "living" (sometimes, for many years) in the "world" of their concepts and models, mathematicians have learned to draw maximum of conclusions from a minimum of premises. After one has formulated some model, it usually appears that in mathematics some work has already been done on the problem, and some methods or even algorithms have been created. This allows to draw in real time many important conclusions about the model. Clearly, if the model looks so specific that no ready mathematical means can be found to investigate it, the situation becomes more complicated. Either the model is not good enough to represent a really interesting fragment of the "reality" (then we must look for another model), or it is so important that we may initiate investigations to obtain the necessary new mathematical methods. The key to all these possibilities is mathematical platonism - the ability of mathematicians "to live" in the "worlds" of the models they do investigate, the ability to forget all things around them during their work. In this way some of them have got the ill fame of being "rusks", queer customers, etc. Thus we can say that platonism is in fact the psychology of working mathematicians (and that it is a philosophy only from their subjective point of view). The above stated picture of the nature of mathematics is not yet commonly acknowledged. Where is the problem, why it is so hard to regard mathematical theories as fixed models? A personal communication of S.Lavrov from 1988: " ... Theorems of any theory consist, as a rule, of two parts - the premise and the conclusion. Therefore, the conclusion of a theorem is derived not only from a fixed set of axioms, but also from a premise which is specific to this particular theorem. And this premise - is it not an extension of the fixed system of principles? ... Mathematical theories are open for new notions. Thus, in the Calculus after the notion of continuity the following connected notions were introduced: break points, uniform continuity, Lipschitz's conditions, etc. ... All this does not contradict the thesis about fixed character of principles (axioms and rules of inference), but it does not allow "working mathematicians" to regard mathematical theories as fixed ones." 3. Intuition and axiomatics The fixed character of mathematical models and theories is not always evident - because of our platonist habits (we are used to treat mathematical objects as specific "world"). Only few people will dispute the fixed character of a fully axiomatized theory. All principles of reasoning, allowed in such theories, are presented in axioms explicitly. Thus the principal basis is fixed, and any changes in it yield explicit changes in axioms. But can we also fix those theories which are not axiomatized yet? How is it possible? For example, all mathematicians are unanimous about the ways of reasoning which allow us to prove theorems about natural numbers (other ways yield only hypotheses or errors). But most mathematicians do not know anything about the axioms of arithmetic! And even in the theories which seem to be axiomatized (as, for example, geometry in "Elements" of Euclid) we can find aspects of reasoning which are commonly acknowledged as correct, but are not presented in axioms. For example, the properties of the geometric relation "the point A is located on a straight line between the points B and C", are used by Euclid without any foundation. Only in the XIXth century M.Pasch introduced the "axioms of order", characterising this relation. But it was also until this time that all mathematicians treated it equally (though they did not realise how they managed to do it). Trying to explain this phenomenon, we are led to the concept of intuition. Intuition is treated usually as "creative thinking", "direct obtaining of truth", etc. Now we are interested in much more prosaic aspects of intuition. The human brain is a very complicated system of processes. Only a small part of these electrochemical fireworks can be controlled consciously. Therefore, similar to the processes going on at the conscious level, there must be a much greater amount of thinking processes going on at the unconscious level. Experience shows that when the result of some unconscious thinking process is very important for the person, it (the result) can be sometimes recognised at the conscious level. The process itself remains hidden, for this reason the effect seems like a "direct obtaining of truth" etc., (see Poincare [1908], Hadamard [1945]). Since unconscious processes yield not only arbitrary dreams, but also (sometimes) reasonable solutions of real problems, there must be some "reasonable principles" ruling them. In real mathematical theories we have such unconscious "reasonable principles" ruling (together with the axioms or without any axioms) our reasoning. Relatively closed sets of unconscious ruling "principles" are the most elementary type of intuition used in mathematics. We can say, therefore, that a theory (or model) can be fixed not only due to some system of axioms, but also due to a specific intuition. So, we can speak about intuition of natural numbers which determines our reasoning about these numbers, and about "Euclidean intuition", which makes the geometry completely definite, though Euclid's axioms do not contain many essential principles of geometric reasoning. How could we explain the emergence of intuitions, which are ruling the reasoning of so many people equally? It seems that they can arise because human beings all are approximately equal, because they deal with approximately the same external world, and because in the process of education, practical and scientific work they tend to achieve accordance with each other. While investigations are going on, they can achieve the level of complexity, at which the degree of definiteness of intuitive models is already insufficient. Then various conflicts between specialists can appear about which ways of reasoning should be accepted. It happens even that a commonly acknowledged way of reasoning leads to absurd conclusions. In the history of mathematics such situations appeared many times: the crash of the discrete geometric intuition after the discovery of incommensurable magnitudes (the end of VI century B.C.), problems with negative and complex numbers (up to the end of XVIII century), the dispute of L.Euler and J.d'Alembert on the concept of function (XVIII century), groundless operation with divergent series (up to the beginning of XIX century), problems with the acceptance of Cantor's set theory, paradoxes in set theory (the end of XIX century), the scandal around the axiom of choice (the beginning of XX century). All that was caused by the inevitably uncontrollable nature of unconscious processes. It seems, the ruling "principles" of these processes are picked up and fastened by something like the "natural selection" which is not able to a far-reaching co-ordination without making errors. Therefore, the appearance of (real or imagined) paradoxes in intuitive theories is not surprising. The defining intuition of a theory does not always remain constant. Particularly numerous changes happen during the beginning period, when the intuition (as the theory itself), is not yet stabilised. During this, the most delicate period of evolution, the greatest conflicts appear. The only reliable exit from such situations is the following: we must convert (at least partly) the unconscious ruling "principles" into conscious ones and then investigate their accordance with each other. If this conversion were meant in a literal sense, it would be impossible as we cannot know the internal structure of a concrete intuition. We can speak here only about a reconstruction of a "black box" in some other - explicit - terms. Two different approaches are usually applied for such reconstruction: the so-called genetic method and the axiomatic method. The genetic method tries to reconstruct intuition by means of some other theory (which can also be intuitive). Thus, a "suspicious" intuition is modelled, using a "more reliable" one. For example, in this way the objections against the use of complex numbers were removed: complex numbers were presented as points of a plane and in this way even their strangest properties (as, for example, the infinite set of values of log x for a negative x) were converted into simple theorems of geometry. After this, all disputes stopped. In a similar way the problems with the basic concepts of the Calculus (limit, convergence, continuity, etc.) were cleared up - through their definition in terms of epsilon-delta. It appeared, however, that some of these concepts, after the reconstruction in terms of epsilon-delta, possessed unexpected properties missing in the original intuitive concepts. Thus, for example, it was believed that every continuous function of a real variable is differentiable almost everywhere (except of some isolated "break- points"). The concept of continuous function having been defined in terms of epsilon- delta it appeared that a continuous function can be constructed, which is nowhere differentiable (the famous construction of C.Weierstrass). The appearance of unexpected properties in reconstructed concepts means, that here indeed we have a reconstruction - not a direct "copying" of intuitive concepts, and that we must consider the problem seriously: are our reconstructions adequate? The genetic method clears up one intuition in terms of another one, i.e. it is working relatively. The axiomatic method, conversely, is working "absolutely": among commonly acknowledged assertions about objects of a theory some subset is selected, assertions from this subset are called axioms, i.e. they are acknowledged as true without any proof. All other assertions of the theory we must prove using the axioms. These proofs can contain intuitive moments which must be "more evident" than the ideas presented in axioms. The most famous applications of the axiomatic method are the following: the axioms of Euclid, the Hilbert's axioms for the Euclidean geometry, the axioms of G.Peano for arithmetic of natural numbers, the axioms of E.Zermelo and A.Fraenkel for set theory. The axiomatic method (as well as the genetic method) yields only a reconstruction of intuitive concepts. The problem of adequacy can be reduced here to the question, whether all essential properties of intuitive concepts are presented in axioms? From this point of view the most complicated situation appears, when axiomatization is used to rescue some theory which had "lost its way" in paradoxes. The axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel were developed exactly in such a situation - paradoxes having appeared in the intuitive set theory. The problem of adequacy here is very complicated: are all positive contents of the theory saved? What criteria can be set for the adequacy of reconstruction? Let us remember various definitions of the real number concept in terms of rational numbers, presented in the 1870s simultaneously by R.Dedekind, G.Cantor and some others. Why do we regard these reconstructions to be satisfactory? And how can the adequacy of a reconstruction be founded when the original concept remains hidden in intuition and every attempt to get it out is a reconstruction itself with the same problem of adequacy? The only possible realistic answer is: take into account only those aspects of intuitive concepts which can be recognised in the practice of mathematical reasoning. It means, first, that all properties of real numbers, acknowledged before as "evident", must be proved on the basis of the reconstructed concept. Secondly, all intuitively proved theorems of the Calculus must be proved by means of the reconstructed concept. If this is done, it means that those aspects of the intuitive concept of real number which managed to appear in mathematical practice explicitly all are presented in the reconstructed concept. But, maybe, some "hidden" aspects of the intuitive real number concept have not yet appeared in practice. But they will appear in future? At first glance, it seems hard to dispute such a proposition. To be continued. #3